Notes from the underground
barang dot sg
Updated 2 December 2023
The surprise exam

1. A cheeky paradox
2. What’s the argument?
3. A better reading
4. Origin of the paradox
5. The birthday party
6. The one-day case
7. The two-day case
8. Faulty logic?
9. The heap
10. Sorensen’s objection
11. References

Other Sites

Paradox Lost (1971), by Ian Stewart.
jaworski.co.uk (archived copy)
2. What’s the argument?

To resolve this paradox, we must first notice that the student’s argument cannot quite be what it seems at first sight to be.

At first sight, the student means to be arguing that the surprise exam is impossible, i.e., that it cannot take place at all. His apparent point is that, no matter when the teacher holds the exam, the class will end up knowing the exam day beforehand, and so the exam won’t be a surprise in the sense that was promised.

It’s natural to read the paradox this way and virtually everyone does so. Indeed, the manner in which the paradox is normally raised invites this reading at once. But a closer look suggests that this reading cannot be quite right.

The student cannot really be arguing that the surprise exam is impossible because, at various points of his argument, he blithely presumes that the class knows that the surprise exam will occur!

This is not obvious but a close look bears it out.

For example, in reasoning that if the exam falls on Friday, the class would know about this by Thursday’s end (because only one day would be left), he presumes that the class knows that an exam is bound to occur.

Thereafter, in reasoning that if the exam falls on Thursday, the class would know about this by Wednesday’s end (by reasoning that Friday can’t be the exam day on pain of failing to be a surprise), he presumes that the class knows that the exam will be a surprise.

But how can the student be arguing that the surprise exam cannot occur if his very argument presumes that the entire class knows that a surprise exam will occur? That doesn’t make any sense. What is the student really up to?